Al Qaeda’s Fantasy
Ideology
By Lee Harris
(Go to Print Friendly Version)
now your enemy” is
a well-known maxim, but one that is difficult to observe in
practice. Nor is the reason for this hard to fathom: If you
are my enemy, it is unlikely that I will go very much out of
my way to learn to see things from your point of view. And if
this is true even in those cases where the conflict is between
groups that share a common culture, how much more true will it
be when there is a profound cultural and psychological chasm
between the antagonists?
Yet, paradoxically, this failure to understand the enemy
can arise not only from a lack of sympathy with his position,
but also from a kind of misplaced sympathy: When confronted by
a culturally exotic enemy, our first instinct is to understand
such conduct in terms that are familiar to us — terms that
make sense to us in light of our own fund of experience. We
assume that if our enemy is doing x,
it must be for reasons that are comprehensible in terms of our
universe.
Just how unfortunate — indeed, fatal — this approach can be
was demonstrated during the Spanish conquest of Mexico. When
Montezuma learned of Cortés’s arrival, he was at a loss to
know what to make of the event. Who were these white-skinned
alien beings? What had they come for? What were their
intentions?
These were clearly not questions that Montezuma was in a
position to answer. Nothing in his world could possibly
provide him with a key to deciphering correctly the motives of
a man as cunning, resourceful, and determined as Cortés. And
this meant that Montezuma, who, after all, had to do
something, was forced to deploy categories drawn from
the fund of experience that was ready-to-hand in the Aztec
world.
By a fatal coincidence, this fund of experience chanced to
contain a remarkable prefiguring of Cortés — the myth of the
white-skinned god, Quetzalcoatl. And, indeed, the parallels
were uncanny. But, of course, as Montezuma eventually learned,
Cortés was not Quetzalcoatl, and he had not appeared on the
coast of Mexico in order to bring blessings.
We should not be too harsh on Montezuma. He was, after all,
acting exactly as we all act under similar circumstances. We
all want to make sense of our world, and at no time more
urgently than when our world is suddenly behaving strangely.
But in order to make sense of such strangeness, we must be
able to reduce it to something that is not strange — something
that is already known to us, something we know our way around.
Yet this entirely human response, as Montezuma learned to
his regret, can sometimes be very dangerous.
An act of war?
n september 11,
2001, Americans were confronted by an enigma similar to
that presented to the Aztecs — an enigma so baffling that even
elementary questions of nomenclature posed a problem: What
words or phrase should we use merely to refer to the
events of that day? Was it a disaster? Or perhaps a tragedy?
Was it a criminal act, or was it an act of war? Indeed, one
awkward tv anchorman, in groping for
the proper handle, fecklessly called it an accident. But
eventually the collective and unconscious wisdom that governs
such matters prevailed. Words failed, then fell away
completely, and all that was left behind was the bleak but
monumentally poignant set of numbers, 9-11.
But this did not answer the great question: What did it all
mean? In the early days, there were many who were
convinced that they knew the answer to this question. A few
held that we had got what we had coming: It was just desserts
for Bush’s refusal to sign the Kyoto treaty or the predictable
product of the U.S. decision to snub the Durban conference on
racism. Others held, with perhaps a greater semblance of
plausibility, that the explanation of 9-11 was to be sought in what was called,
through an invariable horticultural metaphor, the “root cause”
of terrorism. Eliminate poverty, or economic imperialism, or
global warming, and such acts of terrorism would cease.
Opposed to this kind of analysis were those who saw 9-11 as an unprovoked act of war, and the
standard comparison here was with the Japanese attack on Pearl
Harbor on December 7, 1941. To this
school of thought — ably represented by, among others, the
distinguished classicist Victor Davis Hanson — it is
irrelevant what grievances our enemy may believe it has
against us; what matters is that we have been viciously
attacked and that, for the sake of our survival, we must fight
back.
Those who hold this view are in the overwhelming majority
among Americans. And yet there is one point on which this
position does not differ from the position adopted by those,
such as Noam Chomsky, who place the blame for the attack on
American policy: Both points of view agree in interpreting
9-11 as an act of war, disagreeing
only on the question of whether or not it was justifiable.
This common identification of 9-11
as an act of war arises from a deeper unquestioned assumption
— an assumption made both by Chomsky and his followers on one
hand and Hanson and National Review on the other — and,
indeed, by almost everyone in between. The assumption is this:
An act of violence on the magnitude of 9-11 can only have been intended to further
some kind of political objective. What this political
objective might be, or whether it is worthwhile — these are
all secondary considerations; but surely people do not commit
such acts unless they are trying to achieve some kind of
recognizably political purpose.
Behind this shared assumption stands the figure of
Clausewitz and his famous definition of war as politics
carried out by other means. The whole point of war, on this
reading, is to get other people to do what we want them to do:
It is an effort to make others adopt our policies and/or to
further our interests. Clausewitzian war, in short, is
rational and instrumental. It is the attempt to bring about a
new state of affairs through the artful combination of
violence and the promise to cease violence if certain
political objectives are met.
Of course, this does not mean that wars may not backfire on
those who undertake them, or that a particular application of
military force may not prove to be counterproductive to one’s
particular political purpose. But this does not change the
fact that the final criterion of military success is always
pragmatic: Does it work? Does it in fact bring us closer to
realizing our political objectives?
But is this the right model for understanding 9-11? Or have we, like Montezuma, imposed
our own inadequate categories on an event that simply does not
fit them? Yet, if 9-11 was not an act
of war, then what was it? In what follows, I would like to
pursue a line suggested by a remark by the composer Karlheinz
Stockhausen in reference to 9-11: his
much-quoted comment that it was “the greatest work of art of
all time.”
Despite the repellent nihilism that is at the base of
Stockhausen’s ghoulish aesthetic judgment, it contains an
important insight and comes closer to a genuine assessment of
9-11 than the competing interpretation
of it in terms of Clausewitzian war. For Stockhausen did grasp
one big truth: 9-11 was the enactment
of a fantasy — not an artistic fantasy, to be sure, but a
fantasy nonetheless.
A personal
recollection
y first encounter
with this particular kind of fantasy occurred when I was in
college in the late sixties. A friend of mine and I got into a
heated argument. Although we were both opposed to the Vietnam
War, we discovered that we differed considerably on what
counted as permissible forms of anti-war protest. To me the
point of such protest was simple — to turn people against the
war. Hence anything that was counterproductive to this purpose
was politically irresponsible and should be severely censured.
My friend thought otherwise; in fact, he was planning to join
what by all accounts was to be a massively disruptive
demonstration in Washington, and which in fact became one.
My friend did not disagree with me as to the likely
counterproductive effects of such a demonstration. Instead, he
argued that this simply did not matter. His answer was that
even if it was counterproductive, even if it turned people
against war protesters, indeed even if it made them more
likely to support the continuation of the war, he would still
participate in the demonstration and he would do so for one
simple reason — because it was, in his words, good for his
soul.
What I saw as a political act was not, for my friend, any
such thing. It was not aimed at altering the minds of other
people or persuading them to act differently. Its whole point
was what it did for him.
And what it did for him was to provide him with a fantasy —
a fantasy, namely, of taking part in the revolutionary
struggle of the oppressed against their oppressors. By
participating in a violent anti-war demonstration, he was in
no sense aiming at coercing conformity with his view — for
that would still have been a political objective. Instead, he
took his part in order to confirm his ideological fantasy of
marching on the right side of history, of feeling himself
among the elect few who stood with the angels of historical
inevitability. Thus, when he lay down in front of hapless
commuters on the bridges over the Potomac, he had no interest
in changing the minds of these commuters, no concern over
whether they became angry at the protesters or not. They were
there merely as props, as so many supernumeraries in his
private psychodrama. The protest for him was not politics, but
theater; and the significance of his role lay not in the
political ends his actions might achieve, but rather in their
symbolic value as ritual. In short, he was acting out a
fantasy.
It was not your garden-variety fantasy of life as a sexual
athlete or a racecar driver, but in it, he nonetheless made
himself out as a hero — a hero of the revolutionary struggle.
The components of his fantasy — and that of many young
intellectuals at that time — were compounded purely of
ideological ingredients, smatterings of Marx and Mao, a little
Fanon and perhaps a dash of Herbert Marcuse.
For want of a better term, call the phenomenon in question
a fantasy ideology — by which I mean, political and
ideological symbols and tropes used not for political
purposes, but entirely for the benefit of furthering a
specific personal or collective fantasy. It is, to be frank,
something like “Dungeons and Dragons” carried out not with the
trappings of medieval romances — old castles and maidens in
distress — but entirely in terms of ideological symbols and
emblems. The difference between them is that one is an
innocent pastime while the other has proven to be one of the
most terrible scourges to afflict the human race.
But before tackling this subject outright, let us approach
it through a few observations about the normal role of fantasy
in human conduct.
The nature of fantasy
ideology
t is a common
human weakness to wish to make more of our contribution to the
world than the world is prepared to acknowledge, and it is our
fantasy world that allows us to fill this gap. But normally,
for most of us at least, this fantasy world stays relatively
hidden. Indeed, a common criterion of our mental health is the
extent to which we are able to keep our fantasies firmly under
our watchful control.
Yet clearly there are individuals for whom this control is,
at best, intermittent, resulting in behavior that ranges from
the merely obnoxious to the clinically psychotic. The man who
insists on being taken more seriously than his advantages
warrant falls into the former category; the maniac who murders
an utter stranger because God — or his neighbor’s dog —
commanded him to do so belongs to the latter.
What is common in such interactions is that the fantasist
inevitably treats other people merely as props — there is no
interest in, or even awareness of, others as having wills or
minds of their own. The man who bores us with stories designed
to impress us with his importance, or his intellect, or his
bank account, cares nothing for us as individuals — for he has
already cast us in the role that he wishes us to play: We are
there to be impressed by him. Indeed, it is an error even to
suggest that he is trying to impress us, for this would assume
that he is willing to learn enough about us to discover how
best we might be impressed. But nothing of the kind occurs.
And why should it? After all, the fantasist has already
projected onto us the role that we are to play in his fantasy;
no matter what we may be thinking of his recital, it never
crosses his mind that we may be utterly failing to play the
part expected of us — indeed, it is sometimes astonishing to
see how much exertion is required of us in order to bring our
profound lack of interest to the fantasist’s attention.
To an outside observer, the fantasist is clearly attempting
to compensate by means of his fantasy for the shortcomings of
his own present reality — and thus it is tempting to think of
the fantasist as a kind of Don Quixote impotently tilting at
windmills. But this is an illusion. Make no mistake about it:
The fantasist often exercises great and terrible power
precisely by virtue of his fantasy. The father who demands his
son grow up and become a professional football player will
clearly exercise much more control over his son’s life than a
father who is content to permit his child to pursue his own
goals in life.
This power of the fantasist is entirely traceable to the
fact that, for him, the other is always an object and never a
subject. A subject, after all, has a will of his own, his own
desires and his own agenda; he might rather play the flute
instead of football. And anyone who is aware of this fact is
automatically put at a disadvantage in comparison with the
fantasist — the disadvantage of knowing that other people have
minds of their own and are not merely props to be pushed
around.
For the moment I stop thinking about you as a prop in my
fantasy, you become problematic. If you aren’t what I have
cast you to be, then who are you, and what do you want? And,
in order to answer these questions, I find that I must step
out of the fantasy realm and enter the real world. If I am
your father, I may still wish you to play football, but I can
no longer blithely assume that this is obviously what you have
always wanted; hence, I will need to start paying attention to
you as a genuine other, and no longer merely as a ready-made
prop. Your role will change from “born football player” to —
x, the unknown. The very immensity of
the required mental adjustment goes a long way toward
explaining why it is so seldom made and why it is so often
tragically impossible to wean a fantasist even from the most
destructive fantasy.
Fortunately, the fantasizing individual is normally
surrounded by other individuals who are not fantasizing or, at
the very least, who are not fantasizing in the same way, and
this fact puts some limit on how far most of us allow our
fantasy world to intrude on the precinct of reality.
But what happens when it is not an individual who is caught
up in his fantasy world, but an entire group — a sect, or a
people, or even a nation? That such a thing can happen is
obvious from a glance at history. The various chiliastic
movements, such as those studied in Norman Cohn’s The
Pursuit of the Millennium (Harper & Row, 1961), are splendid examples of collective
fantasy; and there is no doubt that for most of history such
large-scale collective fantasies appear on the world stage
under the guise of religion.
But this changed with the French Revolution. From this
event onward, there would be eruptions of a new kind of
collective fantasy, one in which political ideology replaced
religious mythology as the source of fantasy’s symbols and
rituals. In this way it provided a new, and quite dangerous,
outlet for the fantasy needs of large groups of men and women
— a full-fledged fantasy ideology. For such a fantasy makes no
sense outside of the ideological corpus in terms of which the
fantasy has been constructed. It is from the ideology that the
roles, the setting, the props are drawn, just as for the
earlier pursuers of millennium, the relevant roles, setting,
and props arose out of the biblical corpus of symbolism.
But the symbols by themselves do not create the fantasy.
There must first be a preexisting collective need for
this fantasy; this need comes from a conflict between a set of
collective aspirations and desires, on one hand, and the stern
dictates of brutal reality, on the other — a conflict in which
a lack of realism is gradually transformed into a penchant for
fantasy. History is replete with groups that seem to lack the
capability of seeing themselves as others see them, differing
in this respect much as individuals do.
A fantasy ideology is one that seizes the opportunity
offered by such a lack of realism in a political group and
makes the most of it. This it is able to do through symbols
and rituals, all of which are designed to permit the members
of the political group to indulge in a kind of fantasy
role-playing. Classic examples of this are easy to find: the
Jacobin fantasy of reviving the Roman Republic, Mussolini’s
fantasy of reviving the Roman Empire, Hitler’s fantasy of
reviving German paganism in the thousand-year Reich.
This theme of reviving ancient glory is an important key to
understanding fantasy ideologies, for it suggests that fantasy
ideologies tend to be the domain of those groups that history
has passed by or rejected — groups that feel that they are
under attack from forces which, while more powerful perhaps
than they are, are nonetheless inferior in terms of true
virtue. Such a fantasy ideology was current in the South
before the Civil War and explained much of the conduct of the
Confederacy. Instead of seeing themselves as an anachronism
attempting to prolong the existence of a doomed institution,
Southerners chose to see themselves as the bearer of
true civilization. Imperial Germany had similar
fantasies before and during the Great War. They are well
expressed in Thomas Mann’s Notes of an Unpolitical Man:
Germans possess true inwardness and culture, unlike the French
and English — let alone those barbarous Americans. Indeed,
Hitler’s even more extravagant fantasy ideology is
incomprehensible unless one puts it in the context of this
preexisting fantasy ideology.
In reviewing these fantasy ideologies, especially those
associated with Nazism and Italian fascism, there is always
the temptation for an outside observer to regard their
promulgation as the cynical manipulation by a power-hungry
leader of his gullible followers. This is a serious error, for
the leader himself must be as much steeped in the fantasy as
his followers: He can only make others believe because he
believes so intensely himself.
But the concept of belief, as it is used in this
context, must be carefully understood in order to avoid
ambiguity. For us, belief is a purely passive response to
evidence presented to us — I form my beliefs about the world
for the purpose of understanding the world as it is. But this
is radically different from what might be called
transformative belief — the secret of fantasy ideology. For
here the belief is not passive, but intensely active, and its
purpose is not to describe the world, but to change it. It is,
in a sense, a deliberate form of make-believe, but one in
which the make-believe is not an end in itself, but rather the
means of making the make-believe become real. In this sense it
is akin to such innocently jejune phenomena as “The Power of
Positive Thinking,” or even the little engine that thought it
could. To say that Mussolini, for example, believed
that fascist Italy would revive the Roman Empire does not
mean that he made a careful examination of the evidence and
then arrived at this conclusion. Rather, what is meant by this
is that Mussolini had the will to believe that fascist
Italy would revive the Roman Empire.
The allusion to William James’s famous essay “The Will to
Believe” is not an accident, for James exercised a profound
influence on the two thinkers essential to understanding both
Italian fascism in particular and fantasy ideology in general
— Vilfredo Pareto and Georges Sorel. All three men begin with
the same assumption: If human beings are limited to acting
only on those beliefs that can be logically and scientifically
demonstrated, they could not survive, simply because this
degree of certainty is restricted only to mathematics and the
hard sciences — which, by themselves, are not remotely
sufficient to guide us through the world as it exists. Hence,
human beings must have a large set of beliefs that cannot be
demonstrated logically and scientifically — beliefs that are
therefore irrational as judged by the hard sciences.
Yet the fact that such beliefs cannot be justified by
science does not mean that they may not be useful or
beneficial to the individual or to the society that holds
them. For James, this meant primarily the religious beliefs of
individuals: Did a man’s religious beliefs improve the quality
of his personal life? For Pareto, however, the same argument
was extended to all beliefs: religious, cultural, and
political.
Both James and Pareto viewed non-rational belief from the
perspective of an outside observer: They took up the beliefs
that they found already circulating in the societies in which
they lived and examined them in light of whether they were
beneficial or detrimental to the individuals and the societies
that entertained them. As a botanist examines the flora of a
particular region — he is not interested in creating new
flowers, but simply in cataloguing those that already exist —
so, too, James and Pareto were exclusively interested in
already existing beliefs, and certainly not in producing new
ones.
But this was not enough for Sorel. Combining Nietzsche with
William James, Sorel discovered the secret of Nietzsche’s will
to power in James’s will to believe. James, like Pareto, had
shown that certain spontaneously occurring beliefs enabled
those who held these beliefs to thrive and to prosper, both as
individuals and societies. But if this were true of
spontaneously occurring beliefs, could it not also be true of
beliefs that were deliberately and consciously manufactured?
This was a radical innovation. For just as naturally
existing beliefs could be judged properly only in terms of the
benefits such beliefs brought about in the lives of those who
believed in them, the same standard could now be applied to
beliefs that were deliberately created in order to have a
desired effect on those who came to believe in them. What
would be important about such “artificially inseminated”
beliefs — which Sorel calls myths — was the transformative
effect such myths would have on those who placed their faith
in them and the extent to which such ideological make-believe
altered the character and conduct of those who held them — and
certainly not whether they were true.
Sorel’s candidate for such a myth — the general strike —
never quite caught on. But his underlying insight was taken up
by Mussolini and Italian fascism, and with vastly greater
sensitivity to what is involved in creating such galvanizing
and transformative myths in the minds of large numbers of men
and women. After all, it is obvious that not just any belief
will do and that, furthermore, each particular group of people
will have a disposition, based on history and character, to
entertain one set of beliefs more readily than another.
Mussolini assembled his Sorelian myth out of elements clearly
designed to catch the imagination of his time and place — a
strange blend of Imperial Roman themes and futurist
images.
Yet even the most sensitively crafted myth requires
something more in order to take root in the imagination of
large populations — and this was where Mussolini made his
great innovation. For the Sorelian myth to achieve its effect
it had to be presented as theater. It had to grab the
spectators and make them feel a part of the spectacle. The
Sorelian myth, in short, had to be embodied in a fantasy — a
fantasy with which the “audience” could easily and instantly
identify. The willing suspension of disbelief, which Coleridge
had observed in the psychology of the normal theatergoer,
would be enlisted in the service of the Sorelian myth; and in
the process, it would permit the myth-induced fantasy to
override the obvious objections based on mundane
considerations of reality. Thus twentieth century Italians
became convinced that they were the successors of the Roman
Empire in the same way that a member of a theater audience is
convinced that Hamlet is really talking to his deceased
father’s ghost.
Once again, it is a mistake to see in all of this merely a
ploy — a cynical device to delude the masses. In all fantasy
ideologies, there is a point at which the make-believe becomes
an end in itself. This fact is nowhere more clearly exhibited
than in the Italian conquest of Ethiopia.
Any attempt to see this adventure in Clausewitzian terms is
doomed to fail: There was no political or economic advantage
whatsoever to be gained from the invasion of Ethiopia. Indeed,
the diplomatic disadvantages to Italy in consequence of this
action were tremendous, and they were in no way to be
compensated for by anything that Italy could hope to gain from
possessing Ethiopia as a colony.
Why invade, then? The answer is quite simple. Ethiopia was
a prop — a prop in the fantasy pageant of the new Italian
Empire — that and nothing else. And the war waged in order to
win Ethiopia as a colony was not a war in the Clausewitzian
sense — that is to say, it was not an instrument of political
policy designed to induce concessions from Ethiopia, or to get
Ethiopia to alter its policies, or even to get Ethiopia to
surrender. Ethiopia had to be conquered not because it was
worth conquering, but because the fascist fantasy ideology
required Italy to conquer something — and Ethiopia fit the
bill. The conquest was not the means to an end, as in
Clausewitzian war; it was an end in itself. Or, more
correctly, its true purpose was to bolster the fascist
collective fantasy that insisted on casting the Italians as a
conquering race, the heirs of Imperial Rome.
America as a prop
o be a prop in
someone else’s fantasy is not a pleasant experience,
especially when this someone else is trying to kill you, but
that was the position of Ethiopia in the fantasy ideology of
Italian fascism. And it is the position Americans have been
placed in by the quite different fantasy ideology of radical
Islam.
The terror attack of 9-11 was not
designed to make us alter our policy, but was crafted for its
effect on the terrorists themselves: It was a spectacular
piece of theater. The targets were chosen by al Qaeda not
through military calculation — in contrast, for example, to
the Japanese attack on Pearl Harbor — but entirely because
they stood as symbols of American power universally recognized
by the Arab street. They were gigantic props in a grandiose
spectacle in which the collective fantasy of radical Islam was
brought vividly to life: A mere handful of Muslims, men whose
will was absolutely pure, as proven by their martyrdom,
brought down the haughty towers erected by the Great Satan.
What better proof could there possibly be that God was on the
side of radical Islam and that the end of the reign of the
Great Satan was at hand?
As the purpose of the Italian invasion of Ethiopia was to
prove to the Italians themselves that they were conquerors, so
the purpose of 9-11 was not to create
terror in the minds of the American people but to prove to the
Arabs that Islamic purity, as interpreted by radical Islam,
could triumph. The terror, which to us seems the central fact,
is in the eyes of al Qaeda a by-product. Likewise, what al
Qaeda and its followers see as central to the holy pageant of
9-11 — namely, the heroic martyrdom of
the 19 hijackers — is interpreted by
us quite differently. For us the hijackings, like the
Palestinian “suicide” bombings, are viewed merely as a modus
operandi, a technique that is incidental to a larger strategic
purpose, a makeshift device, a low-tech stopgap. In short,
Clausewitzian war carried out by other means — in this case by
suicide.
But in the fantasy ideology of radical Islam, suicide is
not a means to an end but an end in itself. Seen through the
distorting prism of radical Islam, the act of suicide is
transformed into that of martyrdom — martyrdom in all its
transcendent glory and accompanied by the panoply of magical
powers that religious tradition has always assigned to
martyrdom.
In short, it is a mistake to try to fit such behavior into
the mold created by our own categories and expectations.
Nowhere is this more tellingly illustrated than on the
videotape of Osama bin Laden discussing the attack. The tape
makes clear that the final collapse of the World Trade Center
was not part of the original terrorist scheme, which
apparently assumed that the twin towers would not lose their
structural integrity. But this fact gave to the event — in
terms of al Qaeda’s fantasy ideology — an even greater
poignancy: Precisely because it had not been part of the
original calculation, it was therefore to be understood as a
manifestation of divine intervention. The 19 hijackers did not bring down the towers —
God did.
9-11 as symbolic drama
ost of our
misunderstandings of al Qaeda’s goals have come about for one
fundamental reason: In the first weeks after 9-11, it was impossible to determine whether
or not al Qaeda had embarked on a systematic and calculated
Clausewitzian strategy of terror simply because at that date
we did not know, and could not know, what was coming
next.
In the days and weeks following 9-11 there was a universal sense that it
would happen again at any moment — something shocking and
terrifying, something that would again rivet us to our tv screen. And, indeed, the anthrax scare
seemed, at first, to be designed precisely to fit this bill.
It even had something that 9-11
lacked, namely, the ability to frighten people who sat quietly
in their living rooms in little towns across America, to make
ordinary people feel alarmed undertaking ordinary daily
activities, such as opening the mail. But, leaving aside the
question of whether al Qaeda was in fact directly or
indirectly responsible for the anthrax letters, what was most
striking about this episode was the fact that it showed
dramatically that if al Qaeda had elected to launch a
Clausewitzian war of terror against the United States, even
acts of terror on a vastly smaller scale than 9-11 would still be assured of receiving
enormous media coverage 24 hours a
day, seven days a week. Indeed, even if another agent was
behind the scare, it is still hard to understand how al Qaeda
could fail to profit by the lesson the scare taught — that the
American media, by nature, could be trusted to amplify even
the least act of terrorism into a continuing saga of national
nightmare.
But, leaving aside the anthrax episode, there was in fact
no such act committed by al Qaeda in the months following
9-11. Nor does the possibility that
one might still occur change the fact that during this
critical initial period, one did not. This in itself is a
remarkably telling fact.
Acts of terror, as noted earlier, can be used to pursue
genuine Clausewitzian objectives in precisely the same way
that normal military operations are used, as was demonstrated
during the Algerian war of independence. But this requires
that the acts of terror be deployed with the same kind of
strategic logic that applies to normal military operations. If
you attack your enemy with an act of terror — especially one
on the scale of 9-11 — you must be
prepared to follow up on it immediately. The analogy here to
time-honored military strategy is obvious: If you have
vanquished your enemy on the field of battle, you must
vigorously pursue him while he is in retreat, i.e., while he
is still in a state of panic and confusion. You must not let
him regroup psychologically, but must continue to pummel him
while he is still reeling from the first blow.
This al Qaeda failed to do. And the question is: Why?
Of course, given our limited knowledge, it is possible that
al Qaeda did plan follow-up acts of terror but was simply
unable to carry them out due to our heightened state of
awareness as well as our military efforts to cripple al Qaeda
in its base of operations in Afghanistan. But it is hard to
believe that these factors could have precluded smaller-scale
acts of terror — of the kind employed in Algeria and, more
recently, by the Palestinian suicide bombers. What was to keep
al Qaeda operatives from blowing themselves up at a Wal-Mart
in Arkansas or a McDonald’s in New Hampshire? Very little. And
while it is true that such acts would lack the grandiose
effect of 9-11, they would have
brought terrorism home to the average American in a way that
even 9-11 had not done and, as
evidenced by the anthrax episode, would have multiplied
enormously the already enormous impact on the American psyche
of al Qaeda’s original act of terror.
This was the reason why I, like millions of other
Americans, spent the first few weeks after 9-11 either watching tv constantly or turning it on every 15 minutes: We were prepared to be
devastated again. Our nerves were in a state of such anxious
expectation that a carefully concerted and orchestrated
campaign of smaller-scale, guerrilla-style terror, undertaken
in out-of-the-way locales, could well have had a
catastrophically destabilizing effect on the American economy
and even on our political system.
But such Clausewitzian terror is quite remote from the
symbolic drama enacted by al Qaeda on 9-11 — a great ritual demonstrating the
power of Allah, a pageant designed to convey a message not to
the American people, but to the Arab world. A campaign of
smaller-scale acts of terror would have no glamour in
it, and it was glamour — and grandiosity — that al Qaeda was
seeking in its targets. The pure Islamic David required a
Goliath. After all, if David had merely killed someone his own
size, where would be the evidence of God’s favor toward
him?
Are we at war?
f this
interpretation is correct, then it is time that we
reconsider some of our basic policy in the war on terror.
First of all, it should be obvious that if our enemy is
motivated purely by a fantasy ideology, it is absurd for us to
look for the so-called “root” causes of terrorism in poverty,
lack of education, a lack of democracy, etc. Such factors play
absolutely no role in the creation of a fantasy ideology. On
the contrary, fantasy ideologies have historically been the
product of members of the intelligentsia, middle-class at the
very least and vastly better educated than average.
Furthermore, to hope that democratic reform would discourage
radical Islam ignores the fact that previous fantasy
ideologies have historically arisen in a democratic context;
as the student of European fascism, Ernst Nolte, has observed,
parliamentary democracy was an essential precondition for the
rise of both Mussolini and Hitler.
Equally absurd, on this interpretation, is the notion that
we must review our own policies toward the Arab world — or the
state of Israel — in order to find ways to make our enemies
hate us less. If the Ethiopians had tried to make themselves
more likable to the Italians in the hope that this would make
Mussolini rethink his plans of conquest, it would have had the
same effect. There is no political policy we could take that
would change the attitude of our enemies — short, perhaps, of
a massive nationwide conversion to fundamentalist Islam.
The second consequence to follow from the adoption of this
model for understanding our enemy is that we need to
reconsider the term “war” as it is currently deployed in this
case. When the Japanese started the Pacific war by bombing
Pearl Harbor on December 7, 1941, it
was not because Pearl Harbor was a symbol of American power:
It was because it was a large naval base and the Japanese had
the quite rational strategic goal of crippling the American
Pacific fleet in the first hours of the war. Furthermore, the
act itself would not have taken place if the Japanese had
believed themselves otherwise capable of securing their
political goals — i.e., American acceptance of Japanese
hegemony in Asia and the Pacific. And the war would have
immediately ceased if the United States, in the days following
the attack, had promptly asked for a negotiated settlement of
the conflict on terms acceptable to the Japanese.
In the case of the war begun at Pearl Harbor, all the
parties knew exactly what was at issue, and there was no need
for media experts to argue over the “real” objective behind
the attack. Everyone knew that the Japanese attack was the
result of a strategic decision to go to war with America
rather than accept the American ultimatum to evacuate
Manchuria. In each of these cases, war was entered into by
both sides despite the fact that a political solution was
available to the various contending parties. The decision to
go to war, therefore, was made in a purely Clausewitzian
manner: The employment of military force was selected in
preference to what all sides saw as an unacceptable political
settlement.
This was not remotely the case in the aftermath of 9-11. The issue facing the U.S. was not
whether to accept or to reject al Qaeda’s political demands,
which were nebulous in the extreme. Indeed, al Qaeda did not
even claim to have made the attack in the first place! The
U.S. and its allies were placed in the bizarre position of
first having to prove who their enemy was — a difficulty that,
by definition, does not occur in Clausewitzian war, where it
is essential that the identity of the conflicting parties be
known to each other, since otherwise the conflict would be
pointless.
The fact that we are involved with an enemy who is not
engaged in Clausewitzian warfare has serious repercussions on
our policy. For we are fighting an enemy who has no strategic
purpose in anything he does — whose actions have significance
only in terms of his own fantasy ideology. It means, in a
strange sense, that while we are at war with them, they are
not at war with us — and, indeed, it would be an enormous
improvement if they were. If they were at war with us, they
would be compelled to start thinking realistically, in terms
of objective factors such as overall strategic goals, war
aims, and so forth. They would have to make a realistic, and
not a fantasy-induced, assessment of the relative strength of
us versus them. But because they are operating in terms of
their fantasy ideology, such a realistic assessment is
impossible for them. It matters not how much stronger or more
powerful we are than they — what matters is that God will
bring them victory.
This must be emphasized, for if the fantasy ideology of
Italian fascism was a form of political make-believe, the
fantasy ideology of radical Islam goes even one step further:
It is, in a sense, more akin to a form of magical thinking.
While the Sorelian myth does aim, finally, at transforming the
real world, it is almost as if the “real” world no longer
matters in terms of the fantasy ideology of radical Islam. Our
“real” world, after all, is utterly secular, a concatenation
of an endless series of cause and effect, with all events
occurring on a single ontological plane. But the “real” world
of radical Islam is different — its fantasy ideology reflects
the same philosophical occasionalism that pervades so much of
Islamic theology: That is to say, event b does not happen because it is caused by a
previous event a. Instead, event a is simply the occasion for God to cause
event b, so that the genuine cause of
all events occurring on our ontological plane of existence is
nothing else but God. But if this is so, then the “real” world
that we take for granted simply vanishes, and all becomes
determined by the will of God; and in this manner the line
between realist and magical thinking dissolves. This is why
the mere fact that there is no “realistic” hope of al Qaeda
destroying the United States — and indeed the West as a whole
— is not of the slightest consequence. After all, if God is
willing, the United States and the West could collapse at any
moment.
This element of magical thinking does not make al Qaeda any
less dangerous, however. For it is likely that in al Qaeda’s
collective fantasy there may exist the notion of an ultimate
terror act, a magic bullet capable of bringing down the United
States at a single stroke — and, paradoxically, nothing comes
closer to fulfilling this magical role than the detonation of
a very unmagical nuclear device. That this would not destroy
our society in one fell swoop is obvious to us; but it is not
to our enemies, in whose eyes an act of this nature assumes a
fantasy significance in addition to its sufficiently
terrifying reality — the fantasy significance of providing al
Qaeda with a vision of ultimate and decisive victory over the
West.
Fighting an ideological
epidemic
n the initial
aftermath of 9-11, President Bush
continually spoke of al Qaeda not as terrorists, but as
“evildoers” — a term for which he was widely derided by those
who found it offensively simple-minded and childish.
Evildoers, after all, are characters out of fairy tales, not
real life. Who really sets out for the deliberate purpose of
doing evil, except the wicked dwarves and trolls of our
childhood fantasies?
Bush’s critics — who seem unfortunately to have won the
semantic battle — were both right and wrong. They were right
in observing the fairy-tale provenance of the phrase
“evildoer,” but they were wrong in denouncing Bush’s use of
it. For, whether by instinct or by cunning, Bush struck
exactly the right note. The evildoer of the fairy tale, after
all, is not motivated in his conduct by his wish to change the
way other people act: His objectives are not to persuade or
cajole or threaten others into doing as he wishes them to do.
Instead, other people exist in his eyes only as an opportunity
to do evil: He doesn’t want to manipulate them for his selfish
purpose; rather, his one and only purpose is to inflict evil
on them — evil and nothing more.
Rather than interpreting 9-11 as if
it were a Clausewitzian act of war, Bush instinctively saw it
for what it was: the acting out of demented fantasy. When
confronted with the enigma of 9-11 he
was able to avoid the temptation of trying to interpret it in
terms of our own familiar categories and traditions. Instead
of looking for an utterly mythical root cause for 9-11, or seeing it as a purposeful political
act on the Clausewitzian model, he grasped its essential
nature in one powerful metaphor, offering, in a sense, a kind
of counter-fantasy to the American people, one that allowed
them to grasp the horror of 9-11
without being misled by false analogies and misplaced
metaphors. How much wiser Montezuma would have been if he had
said, “I do not know who these white-skinned strangers may be,
or where they come from, or what they want. But that they are
here to do evil I have no doubt. So let us act
accordingly.”
But, Bush’s critics argued, the term “evildoers”
dehumanizes our enemy. And again, the critics are both
right and wrong. Yes, the term does dehumanize our enemy. But
this is only because our enemy has already dehumanized
himself. A characteristic of fantasy ideology is that those in
the throes of it begin by dehumanizing their enemies by seeing
in them only objects to act upon. It is impossible to treat
others in this way without dehumanizing oneself in the
process. The demands of the fantasy ideology are such that it
transforms all parties into mere symbols. The victims of the
fantasy ideology inevitably end by including both those who
are enacting the fantasy and those upon whom the fantasy is
enacted — both those who perished in the World Trade Center
and those who caused them to perish; and, afterwards, both
those who wept for the dead and those who rejoiced over the
martyrs.
There is one decisive advantage to the “evildoer” metaphor,
and it is this: Combat with evildoers is not Clausewitzian
war. You do not make treaties with evildoers or try to adjust
your conduct to make them like you. You do not try to see the
world from the evildoers’ point of view. You do not try to
appease them, or persuade them, or reason with them. You try,
on the contrary, to outwit them, to vanquish them, to kill
them. You behave with them in the same manner that you would
deal with a fatal epidemic — you try to wipe it out.
So perhaps it is time to retire the war metaphor and to
deploy one that is more fitting: the struggle to eradicate
disease. The fantasy ideologies of the twentieth century,
after all, spread like a virus in susceptible populations:
Their propagation was not that suggested by John Stuart Mill’s
marketplace of ideas — fantasy ideologies were not debated and
examined, weighed and measured, evaluated and compared. They
grew and spread like a cancer in the body politic. For the
people who accepted them did not accept them as tentative or
provisional. They were unalterable and absolute. And finally,
after driving out all other competing ideas and ideologies,
they literally turned their host organism into the instrument
of their own poisonous and deadly will.
The same thing is happening today — and that is our true
enemy. The poison of the radical Islamic fantasy ideology is
being spread all over the Muslim world through schools and
through the media, through mosques and through the demagoguery
of the Arab street. In fact, there is no better way to grasp
the full horror of the poison than to listen as a Palestinian
mother offers her four-year-old son up to be yet another
victim of this ghastly fantasy.
Once we understand this, many of our current perplexities
will find themselves resolved. Pseudo-issues such as debates
over the legitimacy of “racial profiling” would disappear:
Does anyone in his right mind object to screening someone
entering his country for signs of plague? Or quarantining
those who have contracted it? Or closely monitoring precisely
those populations within his country that are most at
risk?
Let there be no doubt about it. The fantasy ideologies of
the twentieth century were plagues, killing millions
and millions of innocent men, women, and children. The only
difference was that the victims and targets of such fantasy
ideologies so frequently refused to see them for what they
were, interpreting them as something quite different — as
normal politics, as reasonable aspirations, as merely
variations on the well-known theme of realpolitik, behaving —
tragically enough — no differently from Montezuma when he
attempted to decipher the inexplicable enigma posed by the
appearance of the Spanish conquistadors. Nor did the fact that
his response was entirely human make his fate any less
terrible.
Feedback? Email
|